An Art's Four Campfires Redux
While looking at my stats today I
discovered that a computer game blogger has recently picked up my post about Art's Four Campfires, in
which I explain Scott McCloud's idea that there are four distinct sets of values which motivate artists and shape the work they create. I was
excited that someone was finally trying to answer the open question I
had about how one could apply these campfires to computer games;
while I sometimes play computer games (I recently played through
Bastion and quite enjoyed it), I do not have nearly enough experience
with them, or with even close to enough genres, to be able to talk
intelligently about their form in a way that a Four Campfires
analysis would require. However, I could not remember why I had found
McCloud's idea interesting in the first place,
so I re-read my other posts on the issue (here and here) and realized
that the Four Campfires can support, and provide a partial vocabulary for,
the kind of discussions of art (books, movies, etc.) that I would like
to see happen instead of the ones that often do happen.
In
case you either forget or weren't around when I first wrote my first Four Campfires post
, I'll encourage you to take the link back (here again) and skip to the summary I
gave of the Four Campfires. (They have bold headings and are rather
short, so don't be daunted by the length of the post.) For the rest
of this post I will assume that you know what the Campfires are.
The
first thing I want to note is that the Four Campfires are of very
little use in a proper literary criticism setting.* While once upon a
time literary criticism was, on an institutional level, at least
partly about deciding which works are good and which works are bad,
which works canonical and which works non-canonical, that is no
longer the case. So in my employment of the Four Campfires, I am
departing from my department, so to speak, at least temporarily,
because I think the Four Campfires are most useful when making
value-judgements.
One of
my pet peeves when reading a discussion of art (whether books,
television, movies, etc.) is when the critic devalues the art for
failing to do what that critic wants the art to do. So, for instance,
if a person criticizes a television show because its storyline is
incoherent or because its visuals are sub-par, I can get annoyed.
Specifically, I get annoyed when someone criticizes a work because it
fails to do something other than what the work appears to be trying
to do. If a work seems guided by a Classicist ethic, supported by
Animism, then expecting it to push boundaries is unfair. If a work
seems guided by a Formalist or Iconoclastic ethic, then expecting it
to have engaging characters or a coherent plot is unfair. Enjoying a
particular experience more than another is perfectly fine, but to
criticize a work for being a different kind of work than you enjoy is
not.
I do
not, however, think that criticizing is never warranted.** I think
there are two kinds of situation—and, joyously, they are
frequent—where criticizing is warranted. The first is when a work
is seems to be attempting a particular goal—say, an Animist one—and
fails to do so. In this case, you can discuss how the work seems to
fail at its own goal. As an example, many people feel that shows like
Lost and Battlestar
Galactica failed in their final
seasons to tell compelling stories, and I would take compelling
storytelling to be a primary goal of both shows. Alternately, I found
300 to be an
astoundingly ugly movie; my brother assures me that the composition
of each frame is nearly perfect, and so if I can take that to be an
indication that the director had Classicist goals, I can feel
comfortable criticizing 300 for
its failure to meet those goals. (I could of course be wrong in that
assessment—maybe I have poor taste—but in that case my
criticizing will be inaccurate rather than misplaced.)
The
second kind of situation in which criticizing makes sense is when a work has
negative ideological content. It is in this sort of situation that
criticism overlaps with criticizing: in literary criticism, one of
the things we do most often (though there is a lot more to it than
this) is read texts as embodying and/or containing ideological
content. The contention is that absolutely all texts have some
discoverable relationship to ideology (or, if you don't like
ideology, to worldview or cosmology or belief). Not all authors
intend to make claims about the universe with their texts, but
nonetheless their texts do make some claims. One of the functions of
criticism is to uncover this content. Often scholars in literary
criticism will make explicit or implicit value judgements about that
content. In this sense, the criticism of and the criticizing of a
text overlap.
For
instance, I find 300 an
ugly movie, but if I'm going to criticize it (which I sometimes do)
I'm probably going to do so on ideological grounds. To wit, it is not
only sexist, but it also overwrites classical history in order to
disguise its misogyny. Furthermore, I often make long arguments about
the movie's abuse of history in order to promote ideals, obviously of
an “American” character, that are mainly used to justify imperial
violence. (I had written out that argument in a draft this post, but it took up too much
space and is not necessary for this conversation). Whether or not the director intended
to justify American foreign violence is beside the point; 300 does it anyway and someone needs to criticize it for doing that. If a
piece of art is sexist, racist, homophobic, or whatever, criticizing
the text for that ideology is warranted regardless of the artist's
goals. That said, I will not criticize a work for failing to espouse the particular claims about the world or ask the particular questions about the world that I would like it to espouse or ask; my criticizing is reserved for what the work does do or tries but fails to do, not what I would have like it to do.
To
summarize, I get annoyed when people criticize art for not attempting
the same goals, or holding the same aesthetic values, as themselves,
but I am all for criticizing art for failing to achieve its apparent
goals or for espousing, intentionally or otherwise, dangerous
ideology. To bring this back to McCloud's idea (which was really just
a pretext for ranting on this topic), what I like about the Four
Campfires are that they produce a vocabulary for the kinds of values
which an artist can try to achieve; if I were to start criticizing
the Four Campfires (more than I already have), I would say that they
simply do not produce enough of a vocabulary. But maybe they don't
have to. Maybe they are just a starting point.
(And now that I've thought this through, I'm noticing that I'm doing for aesthetics in this post what I tried to do for ethics in a recent set of posts. Oddly—or maybe not oddly, since aesthetics and ethics are different things—I am much more willing to come to clear conclusions in art than I am in morality. What is odd, I guess, is that in aesthetics I derive my certainty from ethical grounds, which I shouldn't be able to do when I am less certain about those very ethics. But it's only an apparent contradiction, not a real one; while I am not sure how I can be certain of particular ethical beliefs, I know that I am certain of them.)
*On
the note of number, I'm not sure whether to treat “the Four
Campfires” as plural (because there are four) or singular (because
it's one conceptual tool). I'm going with plural because it makes
more sense syntactically, but it's maybe worth pointing out that I'm
thinking about it as a singular tool. Also, if I missed an instance
of singular use when editing, at least you'll know why it was
singular in the first place. It has nothing to do with my usual habit
of writing too quickly and not editing it enough.
**I am
using “criticizing” instead of “criticism” because, in my
vocabulary, “criticism” is the kind of thing that scholars do in
English departments, and it bears more resemblance to the colloquial
meaning of “analysis” than to the colloquial meaning of
“criticism.” I repeat that reviewing books and determining their artistic merit is not that discipline's primary function. I realize the verbal "criticizing" is awkward but it's all I've got.
No comments:
Post a Comment