In my class about library planning and design, we’ve been
listening to architects talk about the libraries they’ve designed and I’ve been
doing research on Arthur Erickson and the West Coast Modernists. A recurring
theme has been the conflict between the architects’ design philosophy and the
libraries’ and librarians’ needs. For instance, Erickson believed that
architecture ought to blur the difference between interior and exterior and
that architects should allow building designs to rise from the site—from its
topography and surroundings—rather than impose them on the site.*
The main gallery, or Great Hall, of UBC's Museum of Anthropology, which is sometimes considered Erickson's masterpiece. |
And this
leads to some beautiful buildings…but when such buildings leaked, Erickson
would say it was merely “part of nature.” Such response is guaranteed to make a
librarian squirm. In order to preserve materials, strict environmental controls
are required. A blasé attitude towards leaks isn’t just impractical, but it
violates some of the fundamental values librarians hold. Or, I should, it is
impractical because it violates some of the
fundamental values librarians hold. I’ve come to understand that
claiming that something is impractical is a rhetorical move that appeals to a
person’s values without appearing to do so.**
Generally, when a person appeals to the practical by saying
that a proposed idea cannot be followed because it is impractical, they are
saying either that 1) the proposed idea is impossible or 2) the proposed idea
costs too much in terms of time, effort, money, space, or material resources.
In the first case, it isn’t actually a case of practicality but possibility,
and so invoking the practical is not quite accurate. In the second case, the
reason they aren’t interested in following through with the proposal is that
its costs are not worth the value the proposal would offer. Therefore either 1)
they do not value the proposal (“This isn’t worth the paper it’s printed on”)
or 2) they do value the proposal, but they value the other things they could attain with those resources more. If a
person says, “Erickson’s design philosophy is nice, but it’s impractical,” they
are either lying about the first part (they don’t think Erickson’s design
philosophy is nice at all) or they have other values which trump the value
the attribute to Erickson’s design philosophy (preservation matters more to them than acknowledging the location of the building). If you think a sports car is too impractical for you to buy, maybe you just don't like sports cars, or maybe you'd rather spend the money on groceries because you value groceries more.
By calling the proposal “impractical,” however, or by
appealing to “practical realities,” the speaker rhetorically obscures the fact
that the assessment involves their own values. Either the proposal is itself impractical, or they appeal to
practical realities. This is a
rhetorical move which makes their assessment sound objective and therefore shuts down further discussion; it is the kind of move
people make when they are trying to finish the discussion, and it is effective
in doing so because it smuggles values into the argument under the disguise of
objective facts. Although I feel like this is always insidious, it is not
always cynically intended. I suspect, for the most part, that speakers either
assume that their interlocutors share their values or do not realize that a conflict of values is at all involved. In that last case, I suspect people’s values are often most
inscrutable to the people who hold them, so they do not realize that a conflict in values is at the heart of the debate. And although this is a move meant to
finish the conversation, I do not suspect that people are being deliberately unfair when they use
it, in the sense that I do not suspect most people are even really conscious of
their rhetorical strategies as they use them. Rather, they have goals, and they
just sort of work toward them as it feels right. So I do not especially blame people for appealing to “practical
realities”; often they are justified in doing so. Nonetheless, it is troubling
as a rhetorical move because it tries to obscure the underlying values in an
air of objective facticity, perhaps even to the speakers themselves.
As an attempt to rectify this, I will define practicality so
that it makes its reliance on values clear:
Practical, adj. Of an object, process, or action, supports or does not hinder the users’ ability to act according to their values and intentions.
--
*Erickson’s design philosophy is more interesting and more involved than my
summary makes clear. Look him up!
**I included a shorter and less aggressive version of this argument in the presentation; I excluded any sense that there's something wrong with appealing to the practical, though, because I didn't want to sound like I was blaming my classmates. Many of them appeal to the practical quite often.
**I included a shorter and less aggressive version of this argument in the presentation; I excluded any sense that there's something wrong with appealing to the practical, though, because I didn't want to sound like I was blaming my classmates. Many of them appeal to the practical quite often.
No comments:
Post a Comment