A Taxonomies for Religions Post
Paul Tillich was a Christian existentialist and philosopher popular in the 50s and 60s and one of the most influential theologians of the twentieth century. He was known for his book on popular theology The Courage to Be and The Dynamics of Faith and his multi-volume treatise of more academic theology, Systematic Theology. He worked by correlating human experience and alienation with Christian revelation. Many people, both academic and not, Christian and not, were attracted by his work, though his influence over contemporary theology has largely waned. (But hopefully it is making a resurgence! While it is imperfect, what I’ve read of it is good stuff!)
Paul Tillich was a Christian existentialist and philosopher popular in the 50s and 60s and one of the most influential theologians of the twentieth century. He was known for his book on popular theology The Courage to Be and The Dynamics of Faith and his multi-volume treatise of more academic theology, Systematic Theology. He worked by correlating human experience and alienation with Christian revelation. Many people, both academic and not, Christian and not, were attracted by his work, though his influence over contemporary theology has largely waned. (But hopefully it is making a resurgence! While it is imperfect, what I’ve read of it is good stuff!)
For
Paul Tillich, faith—or religion—is the state of being ultimately concerned. In The Dynamics of Faith he argues that
people are ultimately concerned with something; they are concerned with
something they take to be ultimate. The Ultimate (that is, God) is a final arbiter
of value: in particular, the Ultimate makes promises and threats. When the
Ultimate promises inclusion and threatens exclusion, it can do so successfully
because the Ultimate is not contingent on anything else and its activities
cannot be thwarted by anything else. When people are ultimately concerned with
something that is not the
Ultimate—success, or humanity, or a flawed vision of God—they are bound for
misery and failure, since the thing with which they are ultimately concerned
cannot deliver on its promises. (His argument gets confusing at this point: he
writes that people are always ultimately concerned with one thing, and as such
all people are religious, but then he writes that atheists are concerned with
competing interests. He seems to contradict himself.)
Tillich’s
opening in Dynamics offers a possible
question, then: About what is a practitioner ultimately concerned? What does it
mean for this idea of the Ultimate to promise inclusion, or to threaten
exclusion?
Because
the Ultimate is not contingent on anything else, it cannot be captured by any
description or formulation humans—inherently limited beings that we are—might
make about it. Thus there can be no perfect dogma about God. Rather, religious
creeds are symbols (signs that participate in that which they signify) and they
only signify according to the community’s language. As the community changes,
and its language changes, the symbol’s ability to signify God diminishes. Thus
any religion that seeks to approach God—the Ultimate—and avoid a false vision
of God must be able to change its symbols (that is, its creeds and dogmas). A
religion, Tillich argues, which honestly acknowledges the ultimacy of God, must
contain a tradition or mechanism of criticism against its own terms. According
to Tillich, Protestantism is the only religion which is capable of this
criticism—that is what he identifies as the Protestant Principle and the
Reformation’s very raison d’ĂȘtre—and
this is why Protestantism is the best and truest religion. (Of course,
according to Tillich Protestantism has largely failed in this regard due the
rise of biblical literalism and inerrantism.) While I disagree with his claim
that Protestantism is uniquely self-critical—Buddhism and Daoism leap to mind
as religions which contain self-criticism in response to the ultimacy of the
Ultimate—I feel like this might make another good question: Does the religious
tradition contain an internal mechanism for self-criticism? Does this religion
insist that the Ultimate, as Ultimate, cannot be timelessly described in creeds
and other symbols, or does it take those creeds and symbols to be timelessly
true?
In
the second half of Dynamics, Tillich
addresses different types of faith. There are two major groupings, each of
which contains a few subgroups:
·
Ontological
types of faith
o
Sacramental
types of faith
o
Mystical
types of faith
·
Moral
types of faith
o
Juristic
types of faith
o
Conventional
types of faith
o
Ethical
types of faith
After
cautioning that all religions participate in all types of faith to some extent,
but human limitation means that religions favour one or two types and only
imperfectly assimilate the others, Tillich launches into a description.
Ontological types of faith
experience the holy in the here and now. Moral
types of faith experience the holy as judgement over the here and now.
Ontological faith is the holiness of what is; moral faith is the holiness of
what ought to be.
Among
the ontological types of faith, sacramental
faith experiences the holy in an object while mystical faith experiences the holy beyond objects and within the
self. Sacramental faith experiences holiness as present within an object, or
sacramental bearer; it describes “the state of being grasped” by the holy
through that specific medium. Sacramental faith runs the risk of forgetting
that the object is merely a bearer of
the holy and that it cannot itself be holy, since it is a materially contingent
object through which the Ultimate reaches humans in their limitation. Mystical
faith, then, seeks to avoid that risk by seeking holiness beyond objects.
Mystical faith does not reject the concrete or material, but rather reaches
toward the ineffable, the ground of all being, the Ultimate. Often mystics
achieve this by going inward through meditation, contemplation, or ecstasy,
identifying the human soul as the point of contact between the Ultimate and
humans in their limitation.
Among the moral types of faith, juristic faith involves obedience to a law, one that permeates all life; the law is felt as both a gift and a command, since life is satisfying within the strictures of the law. Tillich characterizes Islam and the Judaism of the Second Temple as juristic. Conventional faith remains poorly defined in Dynamics of Faith; he gives Confucianism as an example but explains no further. Presumably it involves the maintenance not of divine commands but of social expectations and thereby maintains societal order? Ethical faith demands obedience to justice as a way of reaching God; justice, I think, can be understand as something beyond adherence to rules but instead a commitment to principles which are not easily codified. The Hebrew Testament prophets are an example of this.*
Among the moral types of faith, juristic faith involves obedience to a law, one that permeates all life; the law is felt as both a gift and a command, since life is satisfying within the strictures of the law. Tillich characterizes Islam and the Judaism of the Second Temple as juristic. Conventional faith remains poorly defined in Dynamics of Faith; he gives Confucianism as an example but explains no further. Presumably it involves the maintenance not of divine commands but of social expectations and thereby maintains societal order? Ethical faith demands obedience to justice as a way of reaching God; justice, I think, can be understand as something beyond adherence to rules but instead a commitment to principles which are not easily codified. The Hebrew Testament prophets are an example of this.*
But bear in mind that these forms are usually somewhat interconnected. Sacraments are generally marked out as separate not just in space but in behaviour: in order to approach the bearer of holiness, practitioners must observe ritual purity which resembles, or is, a juristic type of faith. The prophetic wisdom of ethical faith can often derive from mystical faith. And so on.
This
schema offers an obvious set of questions to ask of a religion: Is this
religion more ontological or moral, and how much more? Insofar as it is
ontological, is it more sacramental or mystical, and how much more? Insofar as
it is moral, is it more juristic, conventional, or moral, and how much more?
An issue that will keep coming up in this project is what I’m going to call investments. Tillich is invested in not just Protestant Christianity, but existentialist Protestant Christianity, and this comes through in his starting point (the ultimacy of the Ultimate) and his approach to faith (the human experience of the holy). It’s not just that, for Tillich, only Protestantism can put “Yes” in the column about self-criticism. Rather, Tillich’s desire to ask what a person’s ultimate concern is supposes that, indeed, a person might have only one concern, a view determined in advance by his monotheism, or his particular monotheism (“No one can serve two masters”). And Tillich’s sense of the sacramental bearer kept separate by ritual purity does not seem to make sense in religions which recognize all things as bearers of holiness (and I mean this in the sacramental sense, not just the sense of the goodness of Creation). His idea of what religion looks like comes from the anthropology that preceded him, and that anthropology was … well, it was the 30s, 40s, and 50s.
Nonetheless,
these might be questions we could ask, so long as we watch for when they stop
making sense for a particular religious tradition or a particular religious
person. I’ll write more on these questions of application later.
--
*Tillich
argues that the Roman Catholic Church has been unusually good at unifying all
of these types, but failed—has continually failed—to recognize that the Holy
Spirit demands answers again and again, and has instead rested with its old
answers. The groups of Christians that would become Protestant recognized that
the Roman Catholic Church lost and excluded prophetic self-criticism in its
authoritarian hierarchy, and that the growth of sacramental elements of faith
overwhelmed the moral ones. The first of the two problems preventing a
correction of the second, making the break with Rome inevitable. However, in
response to Roman Catholicism’s overemphasis on the sacramental type of faith,
Protestants have historically emphasized the moral dimension, losing both ontological types of faith. However,
Tillich sees a possibility of reclaiming the unity of all types of faith in
Paul’s description of the Holy Spirit. Make of all this what you will.
**In this chart I’m trying to replicate Tillich’s representations, not supply my own. Feel free to quarrel with his interpretations.
--
Index
**In this chart I’m trying to replicate Tillich’s representations, not supply my own. Feel free to quarrel with his interpretations.
--
Index
No comments:
Post a Comment